24.1. STRONG AND WEAK MEASURABILITY 653

Then since∥∥x∗k − y∗

∥∥< ε, this implies

∥y∗∥ ≥ |y∗ (x)|= |(y∗− x∗k)(x)+ x∗k (x)| ≥ |x∗k (x)|− ε > ∥y∗∥−3ε

It follows that∥y∗∥−3ε ≤ sup

x∈D|y∗ (x)| ≤ ∥y∗∥

This proves the lemma because ε is arbitrary. ■The next theorem is another version of the Pettis theorem. First here is a definition.

Definition 24.1.14 A function y having values in X ′ is weak ∗ measurable, whenfor each x ∈ X, y(·)(x) is a measurable scalar valued function.

Theorem 24.1.15 If X ′ is separable and y : Ω→ X ′ is weak ∗ measurable meaningω → y(ω)(x) is a F valued measurable function, then y is strongly measurable.

Proof: It is necessary to show y−1 (B(a∗,r)) is measurable for a∗ ∈ X ′. This will sufficebecause the separability of X ′ implies every open set is the countable union of such ballsof the form B(a∗,r). It also suffices to verify inverse images of closed balls are measurablebecause every open ball is the countable union of closed balls. From Lemma 24.1.13,

y−1(

B(a∗,r))

= {ω : ∥y(ω)−a∗∥ ≤ r}

=

{ω : sup

x∈D|(y(ω)−a∗)(x)| ≤ r

}=

{ω : sup

x∈D|y(ω)(x)−a∗ (x)| ≤ r

}= ∩x∈Dy(·)(x)−1

(B(a∗ (x) ,r)

)which is a countable intersection of measurable sets by hypothesis. ■

The following are interesting consequences of the theory developed so far and are ofinterest independent of the theory of integration of vector valued functions.

Theorem 24.1.16 If X ′ is separable, then so is X.

Proof: Let D = {xm} ⊆ B, the unit ball of X , be the sequence promised by Lemma24.1.13. Let V be all finite linear combinations of elements of {xm} with rational scalars.Thus V is a separable subspace of X . The claim is that V = X . If not, then it follows thatthere exists x0 ∈ X \V . But by the Hahn Banach theorem there exists x∗0 ∈ X ′ satisfyingx∗0 (x0) ̸= 0, but x∗0 (v) = 0 for every v ∈V . Hence

∥∥x∗0∥∥= supx∈D

∣∣x∗0 (x)∣∣= 0, a contradic-tion. ■

Corollary 24.1.17 If X is reflexive, then X is separable if and only if X ′ is separable.

Proof: From the above theorem, if X ′ is separable, then so is X . Now suppose X isseparable with a dense subset equal to D. Then since X is reflexive, J (D) is dense in X ′′

where J is the James map satisfying Jx(x∗) ≡ x∗ (x) . Recall how this J preserves normsand maps onto X ′′ for X reflexive. Then since X ′′ is separable, it follows from the abovetheorem that X ′ is also separable. ■

Note how this shows that L1 (Rp,mp) is not reflexive because this is a separable space,but L∞ (Rp,mp) is clearly not. For example, you could consider X[0,r] for r a positiveirrational number. There are uncountably many of these functions in L∞ ([0,1]) and it isclear that

∥∥X[0,r]−X[0,r̂]∥∥

∞= 1.

24.1. STRONG AND WEAK MEASURABILITY 653Then since |x -—y* | < €, this implieslly I] = by" @)] = 10" — ae) Oe) +4 @)] = xe @)|— € > Iv" I] - 3€It follows thatlly" || —3€ < sup |y* (x)| < |p" |xeEDThis proves the lemma because € is arbitrary. HiThe next theorem is another version of the Pettis theorem. First here is a definition.Definition 24.1.14 4 function y having values in X' is weak * measurable, whenfor each x € X, y(-) (x) is a measurable scalar valued function.Theorem 24.1.15 If X' is separable and y : Q— X' is weak * measurable meaning@ — y(@) (x) is a F valued measurable function, then y is strongly measurable.Proof: It is necessary to show y~! (B(a*,r)) is measurable for a* € X’. This will sufficebecause the separability of X’ implies every open set is the countable union of such ballsof the form B(a*,r). It also suffices to verify inverse images of closed balls are measurablebecause every open ball is the countable union of closed balls. From Lemma 24.1.13,y'(B@.r)) = {w: |y(@)-a"| <r}= {o:splo(o)—a’) | <r}xe€D_ {:suply(o) () —a° @)| <r}xED= Arevy() (x)! (B@R).7)which is a countable intersection of measurable sets by hypothesis.The following are interesting consequences of the theory developed so far and are ofinterest independent of the theory of integration of vector valued functions.Theorem 24.1.16 If X' is separable, then so is X.Proof: Let D = {x,,} C B, the unit ball of X, be the sequence promised by Lemma24.1.13. Let V be all finite linear combinations of elements of {x,,} with rational scalars.Thus V is a separable subspace of X. The claim is that V = X. If not, then it follows thatthere exists xy € X \V. But by the Hahn Banach theorem there exists x9 € X’ satisfyingx6 (xo) # 0, but x4 (v) = 0 for every v € V. Hence ||x}|| = sup,ep |x5 (x)| = 0, a contradic-tion. HiCorollary 24.1.17 /fX is reflexive, then X is separable if and only if X' is separable.Proof: From the above theorem, if X’ is separable, then so is X. Now suppose X isseparable with a dense subset equal to D. Then since X is reflexive, J (D) is dense in X”where J is the James map satisfying Jx (x*) = x* (x). Recall how this J preserves normsand maps onto X” for X reflexive. Then since X” is separable, it follows from the abovetheorem that X’ is also separable. MlNote how this shows that L' (IR?,m,) is not reflexive because this is a separable space,but L® (IR’,m,) is clearly not. For example, you could consider 2,7 for r a positiveirrational number. There are uncountably many of these functions in L®([0,1]) and it isclear that I Xion) — Zo, |.0 = 1:co